Progressive

 

“You” a very progressive person once told me “are not a progressive”! I suppose this is true if by progressive one means someone who has a grasp on the shape of the future and is busily working to bring it into existence. I don’t have any grasp on the future though if I were to guess I would say that following the convulsions we are likely to go through our social attitudes and practices will almost certainly be radically transformed. This is as likely to be ‘regress’ as anything else. We may become, in some ways, harder, crueler and more intolerant (than we are even now!) as we focus more and more on the basics of subsistence. We might, at the same time, become more generous and community minded towards those in the in-group yet correspondingly more suspicious and resentful of the outsider. Neo-liberal precarity gives us a glimpse of this in the resentful populist and I can’t see general breakdown producing anything but an intensification of this spirit. As scientific and educational infrastructure crumbles I have little doubt that things like magic, sacrifice and taboo will make roaring comebacks and that exhausted and effete Christian churches will pull off no second Carolingian renaissance. We can already see in the Q cult (obsessed as it is with child sacrifice) the shape of future religion even if it retains the external name of Christian. So, I suppose being not bullish about ‘progress’ in terms of the human future I am to that extent not very ‘progressive’.

Really, though, the nub of the accusation is my support, or perceived lack thereof, for what Lyotard called the ‘emancipatory’ meta-narrative. I am, in spite of what the individual cited above claims, largely in favor of the emancipatory meta-narrative. Or I should say in favor of it to the extent that it can be realized without self-contradiction. The question, as even Burke held, is not how much constraint we can impose but how much liberty we can permit. Now, of course, Burke was not a progressive exactly and the very fact that I have cited him shows that I am not exactly one either. The emancipatory narrative looks resolutely forward and I, like Lot’s wife, have looked back to a thinker who opposed the French Revolution (a key moment in that narrative- at least for some).  Burke, in other words, backed the wrong side which is how you get written out of the story of freedom no matter what you might have actually contributed to it. In other words, the emancipatory narrative cuts across the historical narrative and the historical truth of any figure is something I very much look for. Historical truth is something I should distinguish from the empirical science of history. I should probably say, instead of ‘historical truth’ something like the ‘historicity of both truth and praxis’ as one can be a superb ‘historian’ in the academic sense without having a ‘historical’ bone in one’s body. What is more, ‘historicist’ as I may be, I am not a historian and do not have the special kind of patience and attention to detail to be one. A historicist is someone who resists the emancipatory narrative not as a project for the future but as the key to unlocking the past. A historicist is someone who resists what Hubert Butterfield labels ‘Whig history’.

Whig history orders and arranges past phenomena as they anticipate or fail to anticipate the present. Butterfield’s complaint was that such a lens erased the pastness of the past and rendered it only a diminished version of the present. This produced, in his mind, many distorted pictures of things like the scientific revolution where figures were evaluated and judged solely according to the values of the historian, who was usually looking for some hero who anticipated current science and some villain, some superstitious fool or pedant, who did not. Thus, William Harvey is elevated to a hero of science while Robert Fludd is condemned as a mere magician though Fludd was an early supporter of Harvey’s theories and may have influenced them. I have rarely met a devotee of the emancipatory meta-narrative who was not subtly or not so subtly a Whig historian. History is the history of freedom as Hegel said though Hegel, perhaps, now belongs to the dark shadows of the past and is no more to be cited than Edmund Burke! Hegel, of course, understood that the achievements of freedom were always limited and precarious and would agree that the American, French, and other more recent revolutions have left an ambiguous legacy.   

I, though, encounter some people for whom freedom is an all or nothing affair and who think that these past revolutions were no revolutions at all. That or one of them WAS the real revolution and must be whitewashed and justified at literally ANY cost to intellectual or moral integrity! Perhaps this is a distortion imposed by being North American for in North America, and the United States in particular, the emancipatory meta-narrative has mated with what Lyotard would call a prescriptive language game: that of puritan moralism. I have examined this elsewhere but for puritan moralism history is the not the story of freedom but of un-freedom.[1] It is not the story of where the spirit moves but of where it doesn’t. In other words, history becomes the history of evil and we pursue the history of evil because by locating and denouncing it we wash ourselves of its taint. As in the Manichean religion (of which puritan moralism is a species- everything reduces to a theology of some sort) we become good by a ritual separation from the bad and this separation is effected by a ‘critique’ of the past governed by a general hermeneutic of suspicion. The past then becomes a sort of scapegoat that bears the sins of the present.

I don’t play this game at all and I don’t play it for exactly the reason Blake said: the abstract moralism of good and evil crushes the minute particulars of existence. In this case, the particulars crushed are those of the lived imperfection of human existence from which the self-identity of ‘good’ supposedly releases us. This lived imperfection includes tragedy understood as the Greeks (sorry to bring them up again) understood it: human beings do not simply fail by being villains, though in every age there are plenty of those. They also fail by being virtuous: the identity of the good principle with itself does not free us of evil. Our virtue, in tragedy, is our greatest temptation and leads into a ‘sin’ and a tragic fall. This is how we experience the limits of our condition: by tragic suffering. This is how we also learn the limits of the historical horizons we operate under, even the horizon of emancipatory progress, which has fathered as many crimes as simple villainy has and possibly worse ones too. Progress does not free us from tragic suffering and never will. We will always face, as Eliot says, the painful fact of “things done to other’s harm” which once we took for “exercise of virtue”. Thus, ‘progress’ is selling us an illusion if it promises catharsis and liberation from the taint of failure, scandal and sin. This is because we act under the same limitations as agents in the past which is one way in which ‘historicity’ determines our existence. Moralism will never wash us of our sins or release us from the finitude of time and space. It is only through time and process that we learn the tragic limits of our horizons and that we were told very early in the day by Anaximander in his famous fragment! 

It is my considered opinion, from a longstanding habit of reading, that people in the past understood this rather better than we do even if in other ways their vision of the world was much more limited. This is why we should read them not in light of the emancipatory narrative but for themselves. This way we learn the tragic narrative which is one Lyotard does not really consider as far as I can make out. Without the tragic narrative the emancipatory narrative will not emancipate anything but aggressive moralizing and terroristic levelling. Plus, you will not learn the tragic narrative from any other source than the tragedians many of whom are Greek, Hebrew and medieval people who smell bad and have bad teeth. There is no place to go to see the contingency of the present but the pastness of the past for that is the place we can see it not in ourselves. A fish cannot see water but we, being a bit better than fish, can do so, as it were, in a mirror: the mirror memory, personal and cultural, gives us.  We should take full advantage.                     

 

 

 

 

                           

 

 



[1] See https://willsbernard435.blogspot.com/2020/01/catholics-and-puritans.html 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Suspicious: The Hermeneutic of Paranoia

Liar!

Cranks III