Cranks III
In my last piece
I alluded to a kind of crankiness that perhaps deserves more comment. This is
the crankiness exhibited by scientists who comment on matters outside the domain
of the sciences whether these be philosophical, religious or historical. The
interventions of scientists in these domains are, almost without exception,
cranky and it is useful to investigate why. What makes a scientist comment on
these subjects in spite of a manifest unfitness to do so? Why do we need physicists
commenting on the historicity of Jesus or chemists lecturing on epistemology or
archeology? Why do we need the thoughts of ethologists on ‘poetry’ or of
nuclear engineers on the ontological argument? Of course, we do not need such
things at all yet specialists in THESE areas are deeply, existentially convinced
we do. The first thing we must note is that ALL of these people deeply and
correctly resent the intrusion of amateurs in THEIR domains. Yet at the same
time they are incapable of exercising the same restraint they expect of others.
What drives a Dawkins to lecture ignorantly on Keats or a Sagan to offer ridiculously
crude potted histories of science? What makes Neil deGrasse Tyson pronounce on Islamic history with the least confidence of being right? One aspect of this pathology is surely one
of psychological perspective. The individuals mentioned are victims of the
following cognitive bias: if quantum mechanics is a ‘hard’ subject and history is
a ‘soft’ subject then he who masters the first must be more than capable of mastering
the second. Indeed, he must be able to do history more readily and more easily
than any historian who is, after all, only a failed scientist. If the historian
COULD do science he would, but, since he can’t he does the ‘soft subject’ instead.
One the scientist could easily master if he thought it worthwhile to do so
(which usually he doesn’t). Thus, when the biologist or chemist feels the need
to comment on the Greeks or the Middle Ages or the Bible he does so freely and
fully knowing that such subjects are not ‘hard’ and that any claim to special ‘expertise’
in them is phony.
Also, the
scientist knows much more than the literary critic or the social scientist what
knowledge is as he possesses the paradigmatic form of it. If a man truly knows
what real knowledge is, then he can apply that capacity to any subject under
the sun and make progress far more quickly than the pedants who claim a
lifetime’s worth of expertise in the matter. This is why a biologist can tell
us who wrote the plays of Shakespeare far more readily than the phonies who
claim to understand literature but whose purely subjective, arbitrary reactions
to it are an obvious form of bullshit. The ne plus ultra of this kind of
hubris was surely attained by the noted physicist who pointed out, in reaction
to claims of sexual harassment directed at a colleague, that as a scientist he
was far more qualified to assess such claims than the purported victims. As
ridiculous as this sounds, it is only a slight extension of the principle
underlying crank interventions in all the domains listed above. Who but an ethologist
like Dawkins is qualified to judge the value of Kafka’s stories or of War
and Peace? After all he is a man of science and hence a man of knowledge.
If he knows what knowledge itself is then there is nothing, in principle,
he cannot know: the whole contains the part and the general the particular.
This is especially the case given that the usual paradigm of ‘real’ knowledge is
quantitative. English and history involve no math so how could they present the
least barrier to those who can do complex equations? Thus, a delusion bred by a
certain form of scientism may underly the ham-fisted interventions of computer
engineers and quantum physicists in historical, theological and literary
domains they have no business commenting on.
This
is a fallacious pattern of thinking common enough to have a name: the fallacy
of false expertise. If Einstein is an expert on physics, why is he not also an expert
on economics, or sociology or even woodworking? The problem here, though, is
not identifying the fallacy so much as explaining why so many intelligent people
commit it. The answer may well be political. There is a cost to ceding expertise
to another and that is the assumed hegemony of one’s own discipline. Knowledge
is power and where one renounces knowledge one renounces power and prestige.
The greatest offense to any science is the existence of another science to
compete with it for resources and fame. This is why scientific experts
attempt to colonize not only arts disciplines but other sciences as well. How
many climate change deniers or anti-vaxxers are psychologists or physicists rather
than climatologists or epidemiologists? The proponent of any science has a
strong vested interest in the claim that he has the master science and can
therefore comprehend the objects treated in all the others. At bottom, the
physicist who wants to tell us all about the bubonic plague or the inquisition
or who wrote the Bible is engaged in flexing. Of course, another question
remains which concerns the fans of the crank who are so impressed when a
psych prof or statistician shows all the historians and literary critics to
be full of it. Part of this involves the myth of the outsider and the myth of
the underdog. This, though, may require yet another essay!
or, gasp, the philosopher who pontificates on media, memes, anthropology, history, politics, and economics.
ReplyDeleteIt's all a rich tapestry.
ReplyDelete